2021-05-02

Getting History for Atheists Wrong (Again – and not just Probably) — #2

Creative Commons License

This work is licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution 4.0 International License.

by Neil Godfrey

Tim O’Neill makes a statement about history that I have never encountered in any work by any historian explaining to readers what he or she does. The only persons I have heard make the claim come from theological faculties when they try to place the evidence for Jesus on the same (or even higher) level that we have for other historical persons and events. O’Neill points his listeners to the title of his presentation: Did Jesus Exist? Yes (Probably) (link is to the 28 minute youtube video I am discussing). O’Neill explains:

It is … important to note the word “probably” in my answer to the question of whether this historical Jesus existed. Unlike some of the sciences, history can rarely arrive at definitive answers. . . . Historians are like detectives who examine evidence . . . and work out what probably happened. So when it comes to the pre-modern world, the sources, texts, passing references and documents and perhaps archaeology the historians analyse make it impossible for them to do more than than assess what is most likely. (from about 3 min 22 secs into the program)

Anyone who reads any work by historians discussing what they do will recognize that that remark is totally confused about what is the nature of history and the sorts of conclusions that can be drawn from the evidence — at least according to professional historians. At the very best the description might, with some slight modification, apply to a very narrow range of inquiries some historians undertake.

O’Neill continues:

People who like definite answers or proof are usually going to find ancient history pretty frustrating or perhaps disappointing. This means we can’t prove Jesus existed. But scholars can and do conclude that his existence makes most sense.

Given that we cannot give a definitive answer to the question there should be no surprise to learn that there’s no single piece of relevant evidence that definitely shows a historical Jesus existed. . . . The conclusion he most likely did exist depends on several vectors of evidence converging on that as the most likely conclusion.

I – nor you – have never read in a history book that “Rome probably or most likely — we can’t prove it, but it seems most likely from the convergence of several vectors of evidence — once had an empire stretching from Spain to Mesopotamia”, or “Julius Caesar probably existed and was probably assassinated”, or “A probable Spartacus probably led a probable slave rebellion and was probably defeated”.

Where there are questions with unclear answers, historians don’t fudge the odds and say “probably” if there is reason to doubt. They debate, or suspend judgement, or take clear sides because the evidence that does exist convinces them one way or the other. Did the ancient Greeks practice human sacrifice in historical times? Was the practice of temple prostitution practised in the ancient Near East? Did slaves build the pyramids? When questions like these were asked by historians, historians set out what they believed to be their answers — affirmative or negative — and cited the evidence supporting their beliefs. They didn’t fudge with a “probably”. Being intellectually honest types they were willing to concede that they were wrong and ready to change their minds when presented with new evidence or arguments. But that is still taking clear cut sides. It is not a position of “probability”.

Most history is narrative history. The facts are known and the problem for the historian is to decide how best to interpret them and judge the role they played in a narrative about, say, the lead up to a war, or progress toward social changes. That’s where “probably” enters the thinking. Would World War 1 have broken out even if the Archduke of Austria had not been assassinated? Probably. Was the Archduke assassinated? No probably about it.

Eric Hobsbawm

But enough of my words. Hear/read it from some renowned historians themselves:

Eric Hobsbawm

I strongly defend the view that what historians investigate is real. The point from which historians must start, however far from it they may end, is the fundamental and, for them, absolutely central distinction between establishable fact and fiction, between historical statements based on evidence and subject to evidence and those which are not.

There is a postmodernist question about truth but even here we are not dealing with probability but with whether objective truth can be known or not.

It has become fashionable in recent decades, not least among people who think of themselves as on the left, to deny that objective reality is accessible, since what we call ‘facts’ exist only as a function of prior concepts and problems formulated in terms of these. The past we study is only a construct of our minds. One such construct is in principle as valid as another, whether it can be backed by logic and evidence or not. So long as it forms part of an emotionally strong system of beliefs, there is, as it were, no way in principle of deciding that the biblical account of the creation of the earth is inferior to the one proposed by the natural sciences: they are just different. Any tendency to doubt this is ‘positivism’, and no term indicates a more comprehensive dismissal than this, unless it is empiricism.

In short, I believe that without the distinction between what is and what is not so, there can be no history. Rome defeated and destroyed Carthage in the Punic Wars, not the other way round. How we assemble and interpret our chosen sample of verifiable data (which may include not only what happened but what people thought about it) is another matter.

O’Neill compared historians to detectives. Hobsbawm extends that analogy to its logical conclusion:

Actually, few relativists have the full courage of their convictions, at least when it comes to deciding such questions as whether Hitler’s Holocaust took place or not. However, in any case, relativism will not do in history any more than in law courts. Whether the accused in a murder trial is or is not guilty depends on the assessment of old-fashioned positivist evidence, if such evidence is available. Any innocent readers who find themselves in the dock will do well to appeal to it. It is the lawyers for the guilty ones who fall back on postmodern lines of defence. (On History, viii)

Imagine the judge or jury’s sentence: “Guilty (Probably)”

David Hackett Fischer

Speaking of relativism, long before postmodernism made serious inroads into history faculties David Hackett Fischer (or the Historians Fallacies fame) . . .

David Hackett Fischer

There are many objective truths to be told about the past — great and vital truths that are relevant and even urgent to the needs of mankind. But there is no whole truth to be discovered by a simple method of induction. Every true historical statement is an answer to a question which a historian has asked. (Historians’ Fallacies, 5)

So it’s not about what is probably a fact, but about how complete our facts are as an answer to a question. We learn more all the time. Answers change. Sometimes we learn what we thought was a fact was not a fact; more usually we learn more facts. It’s not about what is “probably” a fact, though.

Richard Evans

Richard Evans

Richard Evans found some public fame when he argued before a court the truth (not probable truth) of the Holocaust in a case brought by David Irving. Irving was not arguing that the Holocaust “probably” didn’t happen but that the extent of killing was overstated. Evans and Irving argued facts, not probable facts. The argument was about the meaning and interpretation of the data and sources, not whether what they said was  “probably true” or not. In discussing “historical facts” in his book In Defense of History, Evans gave some insight into how historians approach their sources:

A historical fact is something that happened in history and can be verified as such through the traces history has left behind. Whether or not a historian has actually carried out the act of verification is irrelevant to its factuality; it really is there entirely independently of the historian. This is why historians commonly speak of “discovering” facts about the past, for instance, in coming across a source which tells them of this previously unknown incident at the Stalybridge Wakes. Where theory and interpretation come in is where facts are converted into evidence (that is, facts used in support of an argument), and here theory and interpretation do indeed play a constitutive role. For historians are seldom, if ever, interested in discrete facts entirely for their own sake; they have almost always been concerned with what Ranke called the “interconnectedness” of these facts. Thus the fact of the gingerbread salesman’s death can be used as evidence in a number of different ways, according to the historian’s purpose: as an aspect of crowd behavior in this period, for example, as part of a study of food supplies, as an example of festivals and leisure pursuits, as an element in a history of the Manchester area, and so on. Nevertheless, while it is multifaceted as evidence, the gingerbread salesman’s death is singular as fact. Facts thus precede interpretation conceptually, while interpretation precedes evidence. (In Defense of History, p. 66)

Aviezer Tucker

What about Bayesian reasoning? Isn’t that all about probability? Richard Carrier uses it to argue that Jesus “probably” did not exist. As far as I am aware no theologian uses Bayesian reasoning to argue that Jesus “probably” existed. It’s worth reading what a philosopher of history has to say about historical facts and Bayesian reasoning in history.

Aviezer Tucker

Most research in historiography is actually neither about historical events, nor about their contemporary effects, the evidence, but about the processes that connects events with evidence. (Our Knowledge of the Past, p. 94)

You don’t find many books investigating the historicity of Socrates. You can find more books questioning the historicity of the Exodus, or Moses, even of David. But none that I know of lead readers to the conclusion that those events and persons “probably” happened or existed. They argue a case for or against — or leave the question hanging. Historical Jesus scholars, for example, do not (as far as I am aware) say that Jesus “probably” performed miracles. They say that either the stories are fabricated or can be rationalized as natural events.

There have been attempts to use the full Bayesian formula to evaluate hypotheses about the past, for example, whether miracles happened or not (Earman, 2000, pp. 53–9). Despite Earman’s correct criticism of Hume (1988), both ask the same full Bayesian question: “What is the probability that a certain miracle happened, given the testimonies to that effect and our scientific background knowledge?” But this is not the kind of question biblical critics and historians ask. They ask, “What is the best explanation of this set of documents that tells of a miracle of a certain kind?” The center of research is the explanation of the evidence, not whether or not a literal interpretation of the evidence corresponds with what took place. One explanation of the evidence can be that miracles happened and were recorded. But in competition with the other explanations that biblical critics and historians have proposed to explain such documents, the miracles hypothesis has not fared well. (Our Knowledge, p. 99)

But see again the quote from page 94 above. Questions about the historicity of biblical events do not engage most historians. Establishing the facts, the true facts, is fundamental to the historian’s task. Julius Caesar and every other person critical to a historian’s narrative or argument more than “probably” existed; similarly, every event critical to a historian’s narrative or argument more than “probably” happened. Methods for establishing the facts as facts (more than what we understand by “probable”) are the fundamentals of training of historians. Historians are trained in methods of testing and questioning sources in order to establish the “fidelity” of their facts.

From Wikimedia Commons

Probability enters is at the point we evaluate competing hypotheses or explanations for events or competing conclusions drawn from sources. Recall the old scenario of several witnesses to a traffic accident. That there was a traffic accident is not a “probable” fact but an established fact. But deciding whether a driver or a faulty vehicle or some other factor was to blame does often lead to some conclusions being more probable than others.

Alexander the Great swept across Asia Minor, Egypt, Mesopotamia, through to India. There were wars between Rome and the Jews in Palestine in the first and second centuries. The probabilities related to these events fall upon different proposed explanations for them.

Did the Holocaust probably happen? Did European colonialists probably eradicate indigenous populations? Did Palestinians probably voluntarily flee their Palestinian homes in 1948? Did Jesus probably exist? Facts, not probabilities, are important. The stakes are often high.

From PBS
Michel-Rolph Trouillot

But even in establishing hypotheses and explanations for events historians know the importance of going beyond what is probable. Verifiable facts — not probabilities — matter in history.

Michel-Rolph Trouillot

Is that battle a moment of glory during which freedom-loving Anglos, outnumbered but undaunted, spontaneously chose to fight until death rather than surrender to a corrupt Mexican dictator? Or is it a brutal example of U.S. expansionism, the story of a few white predators taking over what was sacred territory and half-willingly providing, with their death, the alibi for a well-planned annexation? So phrased the debate evokes issues that have divided a few historians and inhabitants of Texas over the last twenty years. But with San Antonio’s population now composed of 56 percent nominal Hispanics, many of whom also acknowledge some Native American ancestry, “the second battle of the Alamo” has literally reached the streets. Demonstrations, parades, editorials, and demands for various municipal or court orders—including one blocking the streets now leading to the Alamo—punctuate the debate between increasingly angry parties.

In the heated context of this debate, advocates on both sides are questioning factual statements, the accuracy of which mattered to few half a century ago. “Facts,” both trivial or prominent in relative isolation, are questioned or heralded by each camp. (Trouillot, Silencing the Past, 9-10)

O’Neill tells his audience

People who like definite answers or proof are usually going to find ancient history pretty frustrating or perhaps disappointing.

I have read and formally studied a lot of ancient history. The experience O’Neill describes is one I have never known. The reason is that historians do not ask questions if there is no evidence to supply us with an answer. They do not play “maybe” games. Ancient history has been described as a “funny kind of history” but not because it is full of “probables”. A well-known historian of ancient history makes it clear:

Worse still, one must consider seriously abandoning some of the most interesting and seductive sections of Herodotus, Thucydides, Polybius, Caesar, Sallust, Livy, Tacitus, Dio Cassius and the rest as primary or secondary sources. There is no choice.

One does not use unreliable sources to construct what a historian thinks “probably” happened. One abandons unreliable sources and turns to questions where it is possible to find answers.

Moses I. Finley

Moses I. Finley 

It is in the end not very surprising that university students of history, with some knowledge of the sources for, say, Tudor England or Louis XIV’s France, find ancient history a ‘funny kind of history’. The unavoidable reliance on the poems of Horace for Augustan ideology, or in the same way on the [play] Eumenides of Aeschylus for the critical moment in Athenian history when the step was taken towards what we know as Periclean democracy, helps explain the appellative ‘funny’. But the oddities are much more far-reaching, extending to the historians themselves in antiquity, in particular to two of their most pervasive characteristics, namely, the extensive direct quotation from speeches and the paucity of reference to (let alone quotation from) actual documents, public or private. The speeches are to us an extra ordinary phenomenon and they produce extraordinary reactions among modern commentators. We have no good reason for taking the speeches to be anything but inventions by the historians, not only in their precise wording but also in their substance. Certainly that is how they were understood in antiquity: witness the discussion in his long essay on Thucydides (ch. 34-48) by Dionysius of Halicarnassus, the most acute and most learned of ancient critics and himself a prolific composer of speeches for his multi-volume Roman Antiquities.

Modern writers find themselves in difficulties. Not only does the position of a Dionysius of Halicarnassus seem immoral – it has been said that one would have to regard Thucydides as ‘blind or dishonest’ – but, worse still, one must consider seriously abandoning some of the most interesting and seductive sections of Herodotus, Thucydides, Polybius, Caesar, Sallust, Livy, Tacitus, Dio Cassius and the rest as primary or secondary sources. There is no choice: if the substance of the speeches or even the wording is not authentic, then one may not legitimately recount that Pericles told the assembled Athenians in 430 BC that their empire ‘is like a tyranny, seemingly unjust to have taken but dangerous to let go’ (Thucydides 2.63.2). I have no idea what Pericles said on that occasion but neither have the innumerable historians who repeat from a speech what I have just quoted. Except for Thucydides and perhaps Polybius, there is no longer any serious argument, though the reluctance to accept the consequences is evident on all sides . . . . (Finley, Ancient History, 12-13)

Probably a fig leaf

Historians have different views on the reliability of various sources. Some are willing to accept more of Herodotus as reliable than others are. What happens, in that case, is that the historians debate. Some say we can rely on X for such and such reasons – and therefore we can say that Herodotus did travel to this or that place and saw such and such an inscription. Others will protest. What I have never found is a history that tells me “Herodotus probably saw such and such an inscription and therefore I am going to write my history in the belief that what Herodotus says is probably true.” What I am far more likely to read is a historian omitting that inscription from his or her narrative entirely or declaring it unreliable and therefore unusable — or a historian declaring that “we know this to be true because Herodotus can be relied upon when he says….”

I don’t think anyone really means “probably” when they say Jesus probably existed. I think the word “probably” functions more like a talisman, or a “get out of jail free” card. It serves to safeguard the speaker from the consequences of making his or her claim on the basis of questionable data. It serves to shut down debate about the grounds for the claim. It serves to prepare the speaker to throw back at a challenger, “Hey, are you some sort of positivist? That sort of history went out of fashion decades ago!” But that response misapplies the word “positivist”. See the Hobsbawm quote above.

What I think is a far more useful historical question is: What is the best explanation for the gospels and epistles and then the emergence of the writings of the church fathers in the second century? Do we need a historical Jesus to explain all of that? What does best explain it all?

By reducing the question to “Did Jesus exist?” we are jumping into an arena of ideological and religious conflicts. It is a valid question but not one that every theologian is prepared to take on with the tools of the professional historian — the ones set out by many of the historians I have quoted above and cite below.

There is no evidence for the existence of Jesus that is on a qualitatively comparable level as the evidence we have for the existence of Socrates or Cicero’s slave or Seneca’s rhetorical rival. If, however, in the minds of some historians, there are “several vectors of evidence converging” in a way that persuades them that a historical Jesus is the “most probable” explanation then they are admitting that a historical Jesus is not the inevitable and only possible conclusion. Otherwise, it would not be a “probable” conclusion. We know what those “several vectors of evidence” are — Paul meeting the brother of the Lord; no one would make up a crucified messiah, etc etc — and each one should be open to critical analysis. There is room for debate on each of those “vectors”. In fact, as far as I am aware, each one of those points is used as a sledgehammer to drive mythicists from the room. Critical response to each of them is ridiculed or misrepresented or simply ignored.

The word “probably” is used as a fig leaf. The one using it usually means “no other explanation for the evidence is allowed”.

Historians work with what they can establish to be facts in order to construct narratives and explanations of varying degrees of probability.

A historical Jesus is not a fact of history — not even probably. A historical Jesus is a hypothesis constructed to explain narratives. So is a mythical or “mythicist” Jesus. But there is a difference. There is tangible, direct and hard evidence for a mythical or theological idea of Jesus. So the question that arises is, “Does the mythicist hypothesis answer all the questions we have about the evidence or do we need a better hypothesis to explain Christian origins or does the historical Jesus hypothesis do a better job?”

Regrettably, one side will continue to say Jesus probably existed when they mean he did exist and no criticism of that assertion will be tolerated. Even the entire discipline of historical inquiry will be misrepresented to maintain that fig leaf.


Evans, Richard J. In Defence of History. London: W. W. Norton, 1997.

Finley, M. I. Ancient History: Evidence and Models. ACLS History E-Book Project, 1999.

Fischer, David Hackett. Historians’ Fallacies: Toward a Logic of Historical Thought. New York: Harper, 1970.

Hobsbawm, Eric J. On History. London: Abacus, 2011.

Trouillot, Michel-Rolph. Silencing the Past: Power and the Production of History. Boston, Mass: Beacon Press, 2015.

Tucker, Aviezer. Our Knowledge of the Past: A Philosophy of Historiography. Reissue edition. Cambridge University Press, 2009.


 

 

The following two tabs change content below.

Neil Godfrey

Neil is the author of this post. To read more about Neil, see our About page.


If you enjoyed this post, please consider donating to Vridar. Thanks!


19 thoughts on “Getting History for Atheists Wrong (Again – and not just Probably) — #2”

  1. Richard Carrier observes a sea change on the reliability of Eusebius, who now is often considered an un-trusted source among current historians. Cf. Corke-Webster, James (2019). Eusebius and empire : constructing church and Rome in the ecclesiastical history. Cambridge. ISBN 978-1108474078.

    “How To Fabricate History: The Example of Eusebius on Alexandrian Christianity”. Richard Carrier Blogs. 20 November 2020.

    • Allen, N.P.L. (2015) Clarifying the Scope of Pre-Fifth-Century C.E. Christian Interpolation in Josephus’ Antiquitates Judaicae (c. 94 C.E.). Unpublished Philosophiae Doctor thesis, Potchefstroom: North-West University:

    [§ 3.5 Hata’s Proof: A Case Study] Hata has shown beyond any doubt that Eusebius, for whatever reason, is not to be trusted when he employs an authority like Josephus to substantiate a particular argument. Eusebius is quite capable on occasion, of brazen dishonesty and hyperbole to obtain his goals.

    It is safe to state that for Eusebius, the end justifies the means. —(Page 265 of 426)

    Cf. HATA, Gohei. 2007. The Abuse and Misuse of Josephus in Eusebius’ Ecclesiastical History, Books 2 and 3, in Studies in Josephus and the Varieties of Ancient Judaism: Louis H. Feldman Jubilee Volume, Eds. Shaye J.D. Cohen and Joshua J.Schwartz, Leiden: E.J. Brill and Co.

  2. Unlike ‘other sciences’, history can rarely arrive at definitive answers.

    lololol,

    a category error – while history involves forensic analysis, and often science, history itself—especially ancient history—is hardly ever, if ever, categorised as a science (if it were, history would have provided or would be providing better answers); and
    even if one does equate history with science, then one would be seeking to repeatedly re-examine ‘evidence’ in light of new ‘evidence’ or new perceptions of existing evidence to arrive at better answers; and one would likely be or best to be doing so in a Bayesian way, something O’Neill decries.

  3. As of the time of this comment I have revised the above post. Some of what I originally copied were only summary notes of O’Neill’s words. I have now corrected those to a transcript of his actual words.

    I am still pretty amazed at his chutzpah for taking it on himself to tell viewers how ancient history is done when he surely has not registered a word about it from historians themselves. I find it hard to think he has even read much ancient history in order to make such statements about it. He is simply making it up. Or rather, I suspect he is repeating what he has heard certain biblical scholars say and without checking their claims has taken their comments as gospel.

  4. Neil, a “probably”, to me, shows progress. Better than a few years back, as Ehrman said (paraphrasing), “whether we like it or not Jesus existed.” A “probably” is allowing room for doubt.

    1. Charles wrote “…a ‘probably’, to me, shows progress”

      Yes, progress, with much credit due to the superlative work of Neil and Tim on Vridar which may then be quoted and cited on the RationalWiki.org article “Jesus myth theory”. For example:

      Jonathan Z. Smith spent a lifetime trying to get us beyond the taboo of suggesting Christians may have borrowed some customs and beliefs from contemporaneous pagan religions. Smith said we should look for analogies and comparisons and we should shun the apologetic, untenable idea of uniqueness. Stop worrying about who borrowed from whom, and start looking for shared ideas and cross-fertilization.

      However, the Bauckham camp seems to have won decisively. For any facet of Christianity, if a modern scholar finds any possible link to Judaism, that must be where it came from. If it sounds remotely close to something in the OT or any Jewish writing, you can stop looking. There are never any Christian precursors in the pagan traditions, and anyone who says differently must be laughed out of the room.
      —Tim Widowfield

      Smith held that the famous “dying and rising god” mytheme was a modern myth—not an ancient one. However Carrier asserts that per the Dying-and-Rising God Mytheme, Smith “didn’t even address 99% of the evidence for it, but flat out ignored almost all of it”.

      While Smith clearly retreated from the “dying and rising god” mytheme, Widowfield observes that, “Smith doubted the usefulness of the dying-and-rising-god motif because it was too Christian-centric and carried too much historical baggage — with scholars who worried about who adopted what from whom instead of what it all meant to adherents.”

      One of the leading scholars on pre-Christian myth, John Granger Cook, asserts—contra Smith—that the continued use of the category of dying and rising gods is justified, writing:

      The resurrection of Osiris is the closest analogy to the resurrection of Jesus, although Osiris remains in the netherworld—wherever it is located. Horus’s resurrection is a clear analogy. The rebirth or resurrection of Dionysus also provides a fairly close analogy to the resurrection of Jesus. The revival of Heracles and probably that of Melqart are also strong analogies.

      Other scholars such as Tryggve Mettinger and Paola Corrente have also concluded that the mytheme was extant prior to Christianity. Corrente notes that “three gods from Mesopotamia, Ugarit and Greece – or say from Mesopotamia, from Near East and from Greece – which are, like, the most certain examples of a god who dies and comes back, are ignored usually.”

  5. One can argue from indicia of probability, or one can argue from historical effect. From the viewpoint of the effect “Jesus” has had on western history, we could say Jesus “absolutely” existed, but the Jesus who affected history was a character in a fabulous story about miracles. Usually, by “existing,” we mean did this person have a biological (factual) existence in the “real” world, and then there isn’t much to hang your hat on, as everyone knows. (How tall was Jesus? What color was his hair? What did he actually do, in the “real” world?) The uncertainty of ancient history derives from the lesser number of indicia of probability that are available to us, but there are usually some indicia. For example, the existence of the Roman Empire is indicated by aqueducts built by the Romans which continue to exist in Europe today, and so on. It makes total sense to me that you, Neil, would focus on issues related to the origins of the stories, rather than the origin of a supposed biological human being, because it is the story that has had the tangible historical and factual effects. Conversely, endless arguments about the “historical” (i.e., biological) Jesus begin to wear me out, because what is the point of a conclusion? You end up with an idea about a “real” human being about whom essentially nothing is known, and whose effect on history is based on an erasure. I can’t forget Bishop Spong’s words: to the effect that Jesus “must have” had some powerful effect on people. “Must have” has no meaning. What had the effect was the magical story. I was also interested by the reference to the legal analytical method and its relation to probability. It is indeed a practical method, but it is also a graded one, with its three gradations of probability assessment, the first two used for civil cases, and the third (beyond reasonable doubt) for criminal cases. If O’Neill wants to use a legal analogy he might consider what the burden of proof is for a historian assessing the probability of the “facts” of ancient history. He would then immediately see that some ancient facts (existence of Roman Empire) are not even remotely on the same level as others (existence of Jesus).

        1. I’m perhaps not well-qualified to answer questions about “moral certainty” in the context of historical inquiry, but I do find it interesting in the Wikipedia entry, that the term has been equated with “beyond a reasonable doubt” in law, about which I know something. Assuming the correlation, I would not consider “moral certainty” to be anything like the standards that either are, or should be used in historical inquiry, because it would wipe out most inquiry, or a lot of it. A great many questions would have to be classified as “we don’t know,” whereas, in most of the histories I’ve read, where (reasonable) doubt exists, the historian will often adopt a plausible scenario and then go about defending it. In my view, as a reader of history (i.e., an amateur), the historian is tasked with determining and defining the level of plausibility, based on all the available evidence, and the gradations are highly various, as quite distinct from the law, where we only have 3 models, and only one at a time. So, my answer to the question would be a qualified “No.”

    1. Clarke Owens wrote: “What had the effect was the magical story.”

      Similarly Dykstra writes:
      “How different is a mythical Christ from a historical Jesus that we can’t know much about with any degree of confidence? … It’s the New Testament Christ that Christianity is all about, not an imaginary historical Jesus that historians construct by accepting or rejecting various parts of the gospels by applying questionable criteria and by mining equally questionable extra-Biblical sources.” [Dykstra, Tom (1 December 2012). “Did Jesus Exist?–-Review of Bart Ehrman’s New Book”. Mandatory for Decent Human Life.]

      • Cain, Benjamin (21 June 2020). “Clarifying and Debating the Christ Myth Theory”. Medium.

      Perhaps the real founder [of Christianity] was a Roman woman named Griselda who was born in 50 BCE and who converted to Judaism, drew pictures of crucifixions, taught nothing, and died peacefully in her sleep. Perhaps by happenstance that woman was at the root of Christian memories, and those memories were distorted over the years, becoming the Christian legend of Jesus Christ by the familiar process in which errors accrue in the retellings.

    2. I like your point about “of course Jesus” existed from the perspective of Christianity’s influence throughout history. (It’s something I’ve tried to address before but with more technical language like “social knowledge”.)

      The uncertainty of ancient history derives from the lesser number of indicia of probability that are available to us, but there are usually some indicia.

      You offer a useful example: aqueducts as a sample of the abundant evidence we have for the existence of Roman domination in ancient times. The point becomes: without other specific types of evidence there would be little justification for interpreting such evidence as proof of a ruling Roman empire. There was also widespread evidence of Greek culture — we could well conclude that Greece ruled the Mediterranean world and not Rome if we are looking at masses of certain types of data.

      But what counts for a fact is quality and nature of the evidence, even a single piece of evidence. Hence my statement that we have more reliable evidence for the historicity of Publius Vinicius the Stammerer than we do for Jesus.

      endless arguments about the “historical” (i.e., biological) Jesus begin to wear me out

      Oh yes. Me too! I have lost all interest in the debate. What interests me is finding the best explanation for the different sources we have and hence the best explanation for the emergence of Christianity. We can’t a prior assume a historical Jesus in such a quest. That would be like having a magic ring that solves every problem for us by a mere touch and rub of the gem on our finger. The way to find a best explanation is to address the evidence within and external to our sources. No appeals to third parties that are contrived only in our assumptions and imaginations.

      I sometimes think I read many more books on non-biblical topics but most of them are historical types of works, modern, medieval and ancient, Oriental and Occidental. In probably every one of them the historians express care to get facts right, to explain how they get facts — not probabilities. The probabilities are left for evaluations of various explanations and interpretations.

      O’Neill reminds me of a rather prominent political figure we saw often in the news not long ago — one who displayed strong narcissistic traits such as overconfidence in thinking he knows a lot more about X than he really does, insulting and minimizing anyone who criticizes him….

          1. Could the penultimate high priest Mattathias ben Theophilus have been the father of Josephus? That is one supposition of that lawyer Joseph Raymond.

            Paul sends out a high five to his “kinsman Herodian”… so much of religion is just another way to control people. Much like “War is not merely an act of policy but a true political instrument, a continuation of political intercourse carried on with other means” as Clausewitz wisely wrote.

            Jesus was just a man but his conception, birth, life, and death must have been all politics in the precarious existence of a client state on Rome’s periphery.

            1. Mattatthias was a very common name — in the top 10 for popularity.

              Ilan, Ṭal. Lexicon of Jewish Names in Late Antiquity. Mohr Siebeck, 2002. p. 56

  6. Why does Tim O’Neill of all people deserve the respect of so elaborate an argument? (Not that we don’t appreciate your efforts, Neil.)

    He is a blogger polemicist, nothing more. Which would be fine, except that he’s always telling the world not to listen to anyone but the tenured academic scholars–well, mainly those who have best-selling books on the evangelic market. He himself is not an academic, nor a scholar, nor a published author (to my knowledge). He rails against bloggers and writers who are far more credentialed than he is (e.g. Carrier). I do not understand why knowledgable, scrupulous, fair-minded debaters of the christian legacy like Neil or Peter Kirby pay him any attention at all. Every single post on his blog is, strangely enough, a defense of some aspect or other of a very Western Judea-Christian tradition. He has one post railing against Catherine Nixey’s provocative but impressionistic book about the horrors of early Christendom (Nixey is also not a scholar, but a journalist and polemicist). O’Neill makes a big show of being the even-handed, rational atheist, who only defends the claims of Christianity against skeptics because he is so darn fair, unlike everyone else on the internet.

    His defense of the partial authenticity of the Testimonium Flavianum is a flashy and elaborate performance devoid of intellectual substance, which on Reddit he was unable to defend without vitriol when I offered the most basic objections.

    O’Neill uses the label “atheist” tendentiously, as though it were a credential or validation of his inevitably Ehrman-esque Jeremiads in the name of Christian-friendly centrism, a Christianity-without-miracles into which the pious believer can simply insert their ignorant will to believe. But please, folks, let no one call O’Neill an apologist.

    There is nothing inherently shameful about being a blogger or polemicist or controversialist or untenured writer or what have you. (That’s me, folks.) But why take seriously his claims to be an authority on history or anything else?

    1. Answer: because many people do take notice of him. Biblical scholars whose blogs feature in the monthly “biblical studies carnival” are among those who have high praise for O’Neill’s efforts to defend their arguments. I think it is important to have a voice available that gives the other side of the story.

      I have been told a few times of some readers who have been wondering about some of O’Neill’s points until they were told to check what O’Neill wrote against my responses — with the result that they appreciated what I had written and saw through O’Neill’s bluster and aggression. Little moments like that make me think my efforts worthwhile to some extent.

      O’Neill has denied it when I reminded him not so long ago that I recall some years back his expressing embarrassment to be associated with atheists when/if atheists entertain mythicism and so question the conventional wisdom. There are suggestions that he does feel embarrassed to be associated with “fringe” theorists who step outside the mainstream.

      Note in the video presentation the times O’Neill refers to “Saint Paul” — not “Paul”. One does wonder about the lingering impact of his catholic background.

      What makes sense to me is that O’Neill is a narcissist who wants to be thought of well and highly. Hence his arguments regularly from the authorities whose praise he earns and his insults directed at anyone who criticizes his points. As an atheist he doesn’t want to be thought of as a freak (for some reason thinking that it harms his image if some atheists are found to be wackos). Consult the narcissist checklists. That’s O’Neill through and through. He certainly has an over-exalted opinion of his knowledge and a quickness to mock and insult and reduce to “nothing” or “nobodies” anyone who challenges him — to mention just two of the checkboxes. Hence his dismissal of my posts as “not worth addressing” because they only pick on “minor points” and I’m only a librarian, oh, and supposedly old.

Leave a Comment

Your email address will not be published. Required fields are marked *

This site uses Akismet to reduce spam. Learn how your comment data is processed.

Discover more from Vridar

Subscribe now to keep reading and get access to the full archive.

Continue reading